August
20, 2002
Introduction
Interviews and introduction by Anthony Dworkin
The
official line from the White House is that President Bush has made
no decision about whether to attack Iraq. Indeed, the President
says that he does not even have a timetable for deciding. However,
the possibility of an attack has been under debate for so long,
and so openly, that most observers take it for granted that the
administration intends to strike against Saddam Husseins regime
within the next six months. The prospect has provoked unease among
some US politicians, and outright protests from many European allies.
Some
of the misgivings relate to practical or strategic questions: How
difficult would it be to win? What kind of regime would replace
Saddam Hussein? What would be the wider consequences for the Middle
East? Alongside these questions, however, there has been increasing
debate about the legal authority under which an attack would be
carried out. After all, the kind of operation that seems to be under
consideration would mark a major departure from accepted international
practice: an attack against a sovereign state, aimed explicitly
at removing its internationally recognised government, without specific
authorization from the United Nations Security Council, not in response
to a prior act of aggression, and carried out not by a multilateral
organization but by the worlds greatest military power, acting
alone or with the backing only of a few loyal allies.
It
is sometimes said that an attack would be justified because of Iraqs
refusal to allow weapons inspections in line with Security Council
Resolution 687, which established a ceasefire at the end of the
Gulf War in 1991. However the resolution did not make the ceasefire
conditional on Iraqs future cooperation with inspections;
instead it said that the Security Council "decides to remain
seized of the matter and to take such further steps as may be required
for the implementation of the present resolution and to secure peace
and security in the area". This seems to imply that another
Security Council resolution would be needed to authorize further
military action, and that has been the position taken by most international
statesmen. For instance, French President Jacques Chirac said on
July 30 that an attack "could only be justified if it were
decided on by the Security Council," and German Chancellor
Gerhard Schroder said there would be no support in Germany for a
strike "without approval of the United Nations".
In
any case, the Bush administration has prepared the ground for an
attack by developing a different justification: that an attack against
Iraq would be an act of self-defence. Because of the new threats
that the United States faces, it is claimed, a proper understanding
of the right of self-defence should now extend to authorizing pre-emptive
attacks against potential aggressors, cutting them off before they
are able to launch strikes against the US that might be devastating
in their scale and scope.
This
guiding principle is being worked up as a central tenet of the United
States strategic posture as a "Bush doctrine".
The fullest exposition was given by the President in a speech at
West Point on June 1. Warning that the United States faced "a
threat with no precedent" through the proliferation of weapons
of mass destruction and the emergence of global terrorism, Bush
said that the traditional strategies of deterrence and containment
were no longer sufficient. Deterrence meant nothing "against
shadowy terrorist networks with no nation or citizens to defend"
and containment could not work "when unbalanced dictators with
weapons of mass destruction can deliver those weapons on missiles
or secretly provide them to terrorist allies." Under these
circumstances, he concluded, "If we wait for threats to fully
materialize, we will have waited too long."
Administration
officials have stressed that the kind of pre-emptive actions that
are envisaged by this doctrine are not exclusively military; nevertheless
it clearly allows for armed strikes as a last resort. Although Iraq
is the most obvious case in which a policy of pre-emptive self-defence
might be invoked, the doctrine is intended to have wider application.
Officials have spoken of a hypothetical case in which Islamic militants
in Pakistan gain control of a nuclear weapon. According to newspaper
reports, some in the administration have raised the possibility
of a pre-emptive strike against the Bushehr nuclear power plant
in Iran, which is likely to become active in the next couple of
years.
What
is the status of pre-emptive self-defence in international law,
and how does it apply to US policy toward Iraq in particular? The
Crimes of War Project asked five prominent international experts
for their views. Although their opinions were divided, they all
recognized that the Bush administrations proposals raise fundamental
questions about the nature and scope of international law.
Self-Defence
in the UN System
The
starting point for any discussion of the subject is Article 51
of the United Nations Charter, which says that "nothing
in the present Charter shall impair the inherent right of individual
or collective self-defence if an armed attack occurs against a Member
of the United Nations, until the Security Council has taken measures
necessary to maintain international peace and security." Although
the wording of the article appears clear the right of self-defence
is generated when an attack occurs, i.e. the attack must
be occurring before the use of force in self-defence is legitimate
our experts pointed out a number of possible ways in which
the picture may in fact be more complicated.
According
to Thomas Franck, Director of the Center for International Studies
at NYU Law School, and author of a forthcoming book on the use
of force in international law, the interpretation of the UN Charter
was deliberately left up to the principal bodies of the UN itself
(especially the Security Council). This has allowed for a certain
flexibility in the interpretation of Article 51, and in practice
the UN has granted some leeway "where there is very clear evidence
that an armed attack, having not yet occurred, is nevertheless imminent
and would be overwhelming, and would make the awaiting of the armed
attack disastrous for the attacked country." Franck argued
that the organs of the UN performed "a sort of jurying function,
in trying to apply the law in a reasonable fashion" in light
of international developments that might not have been foreseen
in 1945.
In
a similar vein, Martti Koskenniemi, Director of the Erik Castren
Institute of International Law and Human Rights at the University
of Helsinki in Finland, said that the right of self-defence
articulated in the UN Charter "should be read rationally against
the useful purpose the rule is intended to serve." Koskenniemi
argued that the purpose of Article 51 was "to protect the sovereignty
and independence of the state," and therefore that a state
that felt its sovereignty and independence to be threatened by the
actions of another country, might be entitled to use force against
that country, even if the countrys hostile actions had not
yet risen to the level of an actual armed attack.
A number
of experts mentioned the fact that the language of Article 51 talks
of an "inherent right" of self-defence, and pointed out
that this has been held by some people to imply that the right of
self-defence that existed in customary international law before
1945 might still apply co-existing, as it were, with the
UN Charter. As Michael Byers, Associate Professor at Duke University
School of Law, explained, customary law traditionally recognized
a limited right of pre-emptive self-defence according to what are
known as the "Caroline criteria". These date back
to an incident in 1837, during a rebellion against British rule
in Canada, when British troops attacked a ship (the Caroline)
that was being used by private citizens in the United States to
ferry supplies to the rebels. After a long diplomatic correspondence
between the US Secretary of State, Daniel Webster, and the British
Foreign Office minister Lord Ashburton, a form of words was agreed
to govern acts of anticipatory self-defence: there must be "a
necessity of self-defence, instant, overwhelming, leaving no choice
of means and no moment for deliberation" and the action taken
must not be "unreasonable or excessive".
When
is a First Strike Acceptable?
If
one accepts that some right of pre-emptive self-defence might exist
under international law, the next question is how far it extends.
Of the experts we spoke to, Byers took the narrowest view of this
point: he said even if there was a right of striking first, it could
only exist when the country affected had no time to take the issue
to the United Nations. Under the wording of Article 51, Byers argued,
"you have the right of self-defence until such time as the
Security Council takes action. And therefore its implied that
if you have the time to deliberate and to go to the Council before
you take pre-emptive action, then you have to go to the Council."
In
other words, Byers argued, the Bush doctrine was clearly illegal:
"Theres no suggestion that Iraq is going to attack the
United States tomorrow or next week, or that any of the countries
that potentially fall within the scope of military action justified
by the Bush doctrine are immediate threats." Rather, Byers
said, the policy was aimed at "effectively closing down dangerous
regimes before they become imminent threats" and thus represented
a usurpation of the Security Councils role in global affairs.
Koskenniemi
disagreed with the argument that the right of self-defence only
existed until the Security Council had a chance to address the crisis.
He said that if the Security Council failed to take action that
was sufficient to meet the threat (which, he suggested, was what
the history of the Security Council would lead one to expect) and
the security of the threatened state continued to be at risk, then
the right of self-defence still existed. "I cannot conceive
of an actual situation where the Councils action would extinguish
the attacked nations right of self-defence," he said.
In
the specific case of the United States and Iraq, however, Koskenniemi
said that he did not see that Iraqi actions posed a severe enough
threat to the United States to justify a pre-emptive attack. As
an indication of what might indicate a sufficient threat, he said
there should be evidence that the Iraqi leadership "is in possession
of some sort of weapon, plus a means to get it to the United States,
plus actually intending imminently to do that
but otherwise
not." (Koskenniemi acknowledged, though, that if he were the
legal advisor to the US government, he might take a somewhat different
view. In the end, he said, the legality of such actions was determined
by how they washed with the international community, and that was
dependent on "a complex mix of politics, culture and other
people just looking elsewhere.")
Eyal
Benvenisti, Director of the Minerva Center for Human Rights at the
Hebrew University of Jerusalem, said the legitimacy of an act
of pre-emptive self-defence depended on whether there were "means
other than actual fighting to prevent the threatened attack."
He compared the situation of a country under threat to that of an
individual under domestic law in both cases, if you acted
in self-defence, you then faced the burden of persuading the relevant
authorities after the event that you had acted reasonably: "You
have to convince the international community that you acted in self-defence,
that you had no other choice, and that is similar to the situation
of an individual within a society. I mean, everyone has a right
of private self-defence, when you are being attacked personally
and you cannot call the police
and then the question of whether
you acted in self-defence will be judged ex post facto."
Terrorists
and Weapons of Mass Destruction
Benvenisti
said he sympathised with the Bush doctrine in one respect
the argument that terrorist groups could not be treated according
to the same rules as ordinary states. Using an analogy from games
theory, he said terrorist groups were not "repetitive players"
who had a mutual interest in upholding the acknowledged rules of
the international system (as states do); they themselves would not
be inhibited in any way by the prohibition on the use of force in
international law. Terrorists, he suggested, were more like criminals
acting on a global scale, and therefore should be treated according
to the "logic of police action". The police can act before
a crime has actually taken place; similarly there would be a case
for taking action against terrorists who had acquired a dirty bomb,
even before there was concrete evidence that they were planning
to detonate it imminently.
With
states like Iraq, though, Benvenisti argued that the conventional
rules still applied. It was essential to the international system
to have a clear principle that "no single country has the capacity
to make a judgement over the intentions of another country".
Therefore if there were still time for diplomacy, a military strike
(for instance against a country that was about to acquire a nuclear
capability) would not be authorized under Article 51. But, Benvenisti
pointed out, acts that were technically illegal might nevertheless
be excusable if their long-term consequences came to be applauded
by the international community.
To
illustrate this, he referred to the Israeli military strike against
the Osirak nuclear reactor in Iraq in 1981. (The point is somewhat
complicated by the fact that, according to some people, Israel has
been in a technical state of war with Iraq since its foundation,
since Iraq refused to join the armistice with Israel in 1949; therefore
it can be argued that the attack was not in any case an isolated
act of aggression.) At the time, the Security Council unanimously
condemned Israels action as an illegal use of force. But now,
Benvenisti argued, "it might be seen differently". After
Iraq invaded Kuwait in 1990, a number of people began to argue that
Israels attack "might not have been such a bad idea."
Extending
this point, Terence Taylor, Deputy Director of the International
Institute for Strategic Studies, and formerly a Chief Inspector
for the UN Special Commission on Iraq, said that the prospect
of Saddam Hussein acquiring weapons of mass destruction was sufficiently
grave that a pre-emptive attack by the United States would be legitimate.
He pointed out that in 1992 the Security Council had ruled that
the proliferation of weapons of mass destruction was a threat to
international peace and security, and said that the danger was particularly
acute in the case of Iraq, given their record: "This regime
has already used weapons of mass destruction against the
Iranians and against their own people
theyve already
invaded a neighbouring state. So the track record is not very promising,
to say the least."
Taylor
argued that an invasion of Iraq might not be politically wise, or
militarily feasible. He argued that it would be good politics for
the United States to try to secure a Security Council resolution
if it intended to attack. But he said that Iraq represented a uniquely
dangerous case, that it was reasonable to think that it could present
a genuine threat to the United States and its allies, and that therefore
military action by the United States would be justified.
The
Dangers of Unilateralism
Franck,
however, argued that it was inherently undesirable for the United
States or any other country to take pre-emptive action unilaterally.
He characterised the difficulty posed by anticipatory self-defence
as that of finding a reasonable middle ground between the reductio
ad absurdum of two extremes: "If you insisted that a small
country wait for a neighbour to attack it with nuclear weapons before
responding
everybody would just say the law is an ass. On
the other hand, if you have a law which says that any country that
feels threatened is free to attack any country from which it feels
the threat is emanating, then you dont have a law at all."
In
the case of the United States and Iraq, Franck sketched out what
a reasonable interpretation of the law would demand: that the US
show other states (starting with the Security Council and NATO)
evidence to suggest that Iraq is supporting the use of force by
terrorist organizations against a member (or several members) of
the United Nations. Without such evidence, "you probably shouldnt
do it, because everybody is going to assume that youre acting
for other motives." That would destabilise the international
system, because other countries would see the Bush doctrine as a
potential threat to themselves.
Extending
this point to a general principle, Franck said that when you had
a rule in international law that had to be interpreted reasonably
(as with the right of self-defence), the process by which it was
interpreted became more important than the substance of the rule
itself. It could not simply be interpreted by a single country,
with no attempt to persuade other countries of the necessity of
its actions. "If the process [of interpreting the rule] is
an entirely unilateral one, in which the strong do as they will,
and the weak have to accept it, then were right back to the
Peloponnesian wars, and I think most countries would resist that."
Conclusion
Among
our experts, the principles of the Bush doctrine met with a wide
spectrum of responses. On one extreme, Byers argued that even if
there were some legal right of pre-emptive self-defence, the Bush
doctrine was so far beyond it as to be transparently unlawful. On
the other, Taylor said that the proliferation of weapons of mass
destruction made the claims of the administration reasonable, when
dealing with extreme cases like Iraq.
Between
these positions, our other experts maintained that some forms of
pre-emptive self-defence were legitimate, but all questioned whether
an US attack on Iraq would meet the necessary tests. Clearly, the
strongest way for the administration to win support for its actions
would be to provide convincing evidence that Iraq is working with
terrorist groups in a way that threatens the use of weapons of mass
destruction against the United States or its allies. Significantly,
the British government is said to be compiling a dossier on Saddam
Husseins biological weapons programme; the Times of London
reported on August 3 that "the latest assessment in Washington
and London is that Saddams plan is to produce a basic weapon
that can be used by a terrorist group to attack the Iraqi leaders
enemies, the United States and Israel." Since the September
11 attacks, such claims have often been floated, but so far nothing
more substantial has emerged to confirm them.
This site © Crimes of War Project 1999-2003
|