August
20, 2002
Eyal
Benvenisti,
Director of the Minerva Center for Human Rights at the Hebrew
University of Jerusalem
The
starting point is Article 51 of the UN Charter, which says nothing
"shall impair the inherent right of individual or collective
self-defence if an armed attack occurs
" with "occurs"
in the present tense. This has led to two differing views. One says
the armed attack must already be occurring, and therefore you have
no right of anticipatory self-defence. The other view says, you
cannot wait like a sitting duck for the attack to take place, especially
in the nuclear era, and therefore you can attack if it can be shown
that an attack against you is imminent in a way that cannot be and
would not be stopped unless you react.
In
any case it is a reaction. You have to show that you are reacting
against an imminent attack, that there is an attacker who is about
to attack. And here the paradigmatic case was for years the Cuban
missile crisis, and there was this famous saying by Myres McDougal
that you cannot wait like a sitting duck for an attack to take place,
if after the attack you wouldnt have the capacity to react,
and the notion of self-defence would be meaningless. The U.N. charter
is not a suicide pact, as its been said.
Now
there is another argument worth mentioning, which says that Article
51 in fact does not grant a right to self-defence. The right to
self-defence, as Article 51 states, is inherent: "Nothing in
the present charter shall impair the inherent right
"
as if the right exists regardless of Article 51, in a way that antecedes
the UN charter. In other words, a right to self-defence exists in
customary international law, and Article 51 does not impair it.
And if you talk about customary international law, you refer back
to the Caroline case, which was in effect a case of anticipatory
self-defence.
Now
if we think that anticipatory self-defence is not acceptable, then
there is no point in us getting further into this discussion. If
we think that anticipatory self-defence can under certain circumstances
be acceptable, then we have to examine to what extent an army can
start the actual fighting, and ask what we have to show in order
to be able to claim self-defence.
And
here the problem of course is, as it was under the Caroline
case, the question of imminence and the question whether there are
means other than actual fighting to prevent the attack. This I think
ultimately is a question of fact. You have to convince the international
community that you acted in self-defence, that you had no other
choice, and that is similar to the situation of an individual within
a society. I mean everyone has a right of private self-defence,
when you are being attacked personally, and you dont have
time to call the police or run away. And then the question whether
you acted in self-defence or not will be judged ex post facto.
In
international affairs, the same rationale applies. A country feels
itself under the threat of an imminent attack and reacts to it,
and it cannot be sure that its act will be interpreted as lawful
by the international community, say by the UN Security Council,
etc. And this gives the correct incentives and precautions for the
states involved. They cannot know in advance whether they are acting
lawfully or not. They take their chances, they take the risk that
if, post facto, their actions are interpreted as a violation of
the law, they will be held responsible. They weigh that prospect
against the risk of not responding at the time for an attack.
This
is exactly the same situation with individuals who are being attacked
and they find that they'd better defend themselves and later confront
the possibility of being brought to justice.
One
specific example we have had was the bombing of the Osirak nuclear
reactor in Iraq by Israel in 1981. At that time the reaction was
overwhelmingly negative. The UN Security Council denounced Israel
for its action, and the United States joined the unanimous condemnation
of Israel. Maybe now it might be seen differently. I am not aware
of specific arguments nowadays but I recall that during the Gulf
crisis in 1991, some said perhaps it wasn't such a bad idea, and
perhaps when we deal with leaders who cannot be trusted this kind
of action might be justified.
You
can look at the law on the use of force and self-defence as a set
of norms that are enforced by the principle of reciprocity. All
states are repetitive players, and they want the rules applied to
them in the same way as others because they can be one day on the
receiving end as it were. And therefore the principle of no use
of force with the exception of self-defence makes perfect sense
under a system of reciprocity, when reciprocity is a genuine possibility.
When
reciprocity cannot be ensured, I think we live in a different world.
If you take terrorists, there is no reciprocity between the attacked
state and the group of terrorists who express no clear interest
in their own survival.
The fact that they can be the target of an attack means little to
them. So I would venture to say that you cannot use the same logic
of no use of force other than in self-defence, when you address
actors who are not repetitive ones but have only one strike, if
you see what I mean. And therefore when dealing with them, I think
you enter into a different way of looking at the prevention of attack
more like a police action.
You
know the police dont have to wait for the criminals to attack.
I think that we have a similar concern here, and one government
versus unidentifiable terrorists or a terrorist group that exists
in different places - there is no reciprocity between the two. If
you take say the government of Iraq, a stable government that is
sovereign and is a repetitive player. It may not have the same leadership
through time, but it's going to be the same country, the same people,
and they understand that, they internalise the consequences of an
act of war.
Terrorists
are not the same in that sense. They seek war and they are not intimidated
by international law on the use of force, they are not intimidated
by the prohibition and granted they are not inhibited by that, then
there's no sense in using a law that applies to reciprocal relationships
towards them. Now this I would venture to say is why we should differentiate
between the usual question of whether or not to attack a nuclear
reactor of a state or a government we don't trust, and whether to
attack terrorists who have say a dirty bomb or something, or are
about to get a dirty bomb.
In
the case of terrorists who have a dirty bomb, I would say we have
to apply a different logic, a logic of police action rather than
the logic that I said of reciprocal relationships. When we have
a stable government on the other hand, say we go back to Iraq in
1981, then I think it would be more difficult to explain why it
is legal to strike first well in advance.
In
the particular case of Iraq, Israel was technically in a state of
war with Iraq. Iraq refused to sign the amnesty with Israel in 1949
and therefore it was arguably legal for Israel to strike. This is
a claim that is not accepted by a number of people, but it clouds
the picture.
I would
say this. If there were a normal relationship between two countries,
for example Israel and Pakistan, Pakistan wanting to be the first
to construct the Arab nuclear weapon, then I would say you would
not be able to justify such an attack under the principle of anticipatory
self-defence.
However,
I would suggest that even if an anticipatory attack is unlawful
under Article 51 and customary international law, it doesn't necessarily
mean that if someone used their power in anticipatory self-defence
they would be condemned by the UN or brought before the ICC. It
could be unlawful but excusable.
You
want to provide clear norms that no single country has the capacity
to make a judgment over the action of another country, or the intentions
of another country. Therefore you say, with regard to anticipatory
self-defence, if there is still time to prevent it or still time
for diplomacy, then you should wait and see. If you chose to act
under those circumstances, it would be a violation of Article 51.
Still there might be no sanctions, no condemnation for the act taken
there is room for discretion as to the consequences of an
illegal action.
Similarly,
let's take what happened in Kosovo. The NATO attack, many people
argue, was not a legal act, but it was excusable after the act,
ex post facto, because of the humanitarian situation that developed
immediately following or immediately before the attack. So what
I want to say, there is a third possibility of finessing the consequences
of the illegal action, and you actually know it ex post facto. Say
the Israeli attack on Osirak, at the time it was considered unlawful
but since then in the 1980s there was the use of chemical
weapons against the Kurds and against the Iranians, and there was
the 1990 invasion of Kuwait, and you could then realise that the
intentions of Saddam Hussein were not pure, and this gives you in
retrospect a new sense of what could have happened had Israel not
bombed the nuclear reactor.
You
know we live in a world of uncertainties. We don't know what will
happen if we do this, we don't know what will happen if we don't
do this, so there's two ways to look at it - in advance, and ex
post facto. Sometimes you know better ex post facto and this gives
you an excuse for what initially was a violation of the law, but
eventually becomes excusable.
So
I would say if the US decides to strike facilities where nuclear
weapons are being developed, it takes the risk that it may be deemed
a violation of the law and also not seen as justifiable. Of course
for the US it's not a real threat, because its position in the world
means it can escape sanction. For Israel it's more so which
leads some to say well, this provision doesn't make sense, because
it gives the US anyway the right to do whatever it wants. But we
live in a world of second-best - this is the least worst situation,
where you would say it could be a violation of the law, probably
it is not a valid case of anticipatory self-defence, but it is a
potentially excusable action.
If
we take a related issue, the issue of humanitarian intervention,
many people say, I think rightly, that humanitarian intervention
has been ultimately accepted in the 1990s, though it was debated
earlier. And there was an evolution of the law and pre-emptive self-defence
may be another evolution of the law with the same concerns. Again
it's a question of the allocation of risks. What do we fear more?
Because indeed the UN charter is not a suicide pact, we have to
assess what is worse, the situation where you have the ability of
one country to strike against another, if there is threat of nuclear
weapons, or where you dont. And ultimately it's a question
for the international community to decide and I think we'll see
an evolution in that direction.
This site © Crimes of War Project 1999-2003
|