September
28, 2001
David
Turns
LL.M (London), Barrister, Lecturer in Law, The Liverpool
Law School
The
attacks on the WTC and the Pentagon were definitely not an act of
war in any legal sense, because international law no longer speaks
in terms of wars but of armed conflicts,
usually understood to be between States (although internal conflicts
of great intensity may also be included). The term "act of
war" is now only used rhetorically by States that feel threatened
by a particular hostile activity; it has to all intents and purposes
lost the legal significance it had pre-1945, when it signified a
hostile act terminating the operation of normal peacetime international
law between the belligerents and activating the provisions of the
jus in bello.
I suspect that when President Bush employed the term "act of
war" he did so with no inkling of any possible legal connotations.
In my view it was used entirely rhetorically, for domestic political,
media, and popular consumption with the effect (probably
intended) of a warning of impending military action by U.S. armed
forces.
Individuals or groups cannot be "at war" with States,
for the same reason that the September 11 attacks cannot be regarded
as an "act of war" in any legally meaningful sense. In
the parlance of international law, "armed conflict" requires
two or more State belligerents, or a conflict within one State,
but with a high threshold of intensity. "Isolated and sporadic
acts of terrorism" are expressly excluded, and there
is a requirement that the non-State belligerent be in control of
territory within the State and be capable of mounting "sustained
and concerted military operations".
There seems little doubt that the September 11 attacks will pose
a challenge to the future development of the legal definition of
"armed conflict" and the specific rules applicable in
such conflicts. There is a real risk that 21st Century "asymmetric"
conflicts, such as those opposing one or more States and terrorist
organizations without a clear territorial link, will increasingly
subvert the traditional inter-State or internal rebellion scenarios
that have so far been at the heart of the jus in bello.
This does not mean that we are unable to define the attacks at all.
The destruction of the WTC can undoubtedly be considered an act
of terrorism under Article 2(1) of the 1998 International Convention
for the Suppression of Terrorist Bombings:
"Any
person commits an offence within the meaning of this Convention
if that person unlawfully and intentionally delivers, places,
discharges or detonates an explosive or other lethal device in,
into or against a place of public use, a State or government facility,
a public transportation system or an infrastructure facility:
(a) With the intent to cause death or serious bodily injury; or
(b) With the intent to cause extensive destruction of such a place,
facility or system, where such destruction results in or is likely
to result in major economic loss".
The
attacks may also be viewed, for international law purposes, as violating
the 1970 Hague Convention for the Suppression of the Unlawful Seizure
of Aircraft.
For domestic law purposes, they would obviously amount to common
crimes (murder, conspiracy), albeit on a dramatic scale. The categories
of terrorism and common crimes are not mutually exclusive, although,
in the absence of an international tribunal with appropriate jurisdiction,
the applicability of charges formulated under the conventions mentioned
above would depend on the extent to which those conventions had
been incorporated into the domestic law of the State concerned.
One could make the argument that the attack on the WTC was a crime
against humanity, because it was clearly targeted at a civilian
population. But international case law is as yet divided on how
to define the requirements of this crime. The main areas of disagreement
concern 1) whether a crime against humanity can occur in peacetime,
or whether there must be a state of armed conflict; 2) whether a
single atrocious act may qualify, or whether there must be a pattern,
or campaign, of actions; and 3) whether there was must be State
participation or endorsement of the action in question.
The 1998 Statute of the International Criminal Court
does not specify any requirement of an armed conflict. Article 5
of the ICTY Statute requires a nexus to an armed conflict, but this
document was intended only for the purposes of the Tribunal and
not for international law in general. The case rulings of the ICTY
tend to veer away from absolutely requiring a nexus to armed conflict.1
A more difficult question is whether an isolated act can amount
to a crime against humanity. On this point, the ICTY has issued
contradictory statements. In The Prosecutor v. Kupreskic et al.
(January 14, 2000), it noted that a crime against humanity is
normally understood to occur within a "course of conduct."
However, in the next sentence and accompanying footnotes,
the ruling went on to quote from the Trial Chambers decision
in The Prosecutor v. Tadic (May 7, 1997): "in certain
circumstances, a single act [has qualified] when it occurred within
the necessary context." While it might credibly be suggested
that the "necessary context" of the attack on the WTC
is a campaign of terrorism against the U.S., international case
law has traditionally required such context to be in the form of
a plan or policy formulated, or at least tolerated, by a State or
de facto governmental authority. If this is correct, it would
have to be proved that such an entity sponsored, or at least tolerated,
the attack on the WTC.
On that issue, the present position is, to put it
mildly, confused. In Tadi_, the ICTY stated that while crimes
against humanity "are not isolated, random acts of individuals
[deliberately targeting a civilian population]"
this
no longer needed to be in the form of a State policy. In The
Prosecutor v. Nikoli2 , it was
stated that the acts did not need to be part of a State policy as
such, but could not be the work of isolated individuals acting alone.
On the other hand, national decisions in Canada (Reg. v. Finta,
1994) and France (Barbie, 1988, and Touvier, 1992)
have strongly emphasized the requirement of a State policy. In Kupreskic,
the ICTY concluded its discussion of this difficult and controversial
issue with the tentative suggestion that, in cases where there the
perpetrators of crimes against humanity have no official status
and do not act on behalf of any governmental authority, "some
sort of explicit or implicit approval or endorsement by State or
governmental authorities is required, or else
the offense
[must] be clearly encouraged by a general governmental policy or
clearly fit within such a policy."3
This being the current state of international law as pronounced
by an authoritative international tribunal, I would conclude that
in the last analysis, the attack on the WTC probably cannot be correctly
regarded as a crime against humanity. However, given the contradictions
and uncertainties manifest in the ICTYs discussion over a
range of cases, I would not exclude the possibility that international
law could be developed in future so as to assimilate terrorist acts
targeted exclusively against civilian populations to crimes against
humanity. Moreover, the ICC Statutes reference to the definition
of crimes against humanity as being part of "a State or organizational
policy" might lend support to such a future development, if
terrorist organizations are deemed to be sufficiently "organizational".
The attack on the Pentagon, in my view, cannot be
considered a crime against humanity because of the military nature
of many of the buildings occupants and its function as a command
and control center for U.S. armed forces. The mere presence of civilians
among a target group also including military personnel is not sufficient
to transform such an act into a crime against humanity, as the latter
must be directed against a civilian population as such.4
In the catalogue of international crimes included in the September
11 attacks, I would not include hostage-taking. This is because
the hijackers did not compel a third party to do or abstain from
doing any act, as specified in Article 1(1) of the 1979 International
Convention against the Taking of Hostages. The acts committed were
clearly criminal, but the relevant anti-terrorist convention does
not make them into international crimes (i.e. direct violations
of international law) as such; it merely requires States Parties
to criminalise such conduct in their domestic law and to co-operate
with other States in the investigation and prosecution of such conduct.
Of course, any State military response to the attacks of September
11 is constrained at all times by international humanitarian law.
At its most basic, this includes, but is not limited to, the requirements
to discriminate between military and civilian targets, and to balance
proportionality against considerations of military necessity in
inflicting civilian casualties and collateral damage. It is forbidden
to attack civilians or civilian objects as such and to use weapons
which will, or are likely to, cause unnecessary suffering. Although
specific treaty instruments enshrining these rules may not always
be applicable per se (e.g. the U.S. is not technically bound
by the strict letter of the 1977 Protocol I Additional to the 1949
Geneva Conventions because it has never ratified the Protocol),
most IHL provisions are now considered to be part of customary international
law and therefore legally binding on all States. Non-State actors
in an international armed conflict are in much more obscure position,
as they cannot be parties to international agreements. International
humanitarian law would regard them as unlawful combatants not entitled
to the conflict-specific protection laid down in that body of law,
but the principles of humanity and reciprocity would suggest that,
as a minimum, they should enjoy fundamental guarantees of human
rights on capture by State armed forces, who could nevertheless
try them for criminal acts committed prior to capture.
A State has the right in international law to defend itself against
the perpetrators of an armed attack on its territory, which can
include a terrorist attack. Attacks on any States proved to be behind
the attacks would also be justifiable on the basis of self-defense.
As noted above, any action undertaken in self-defense will have
to respect the requirements of necessity and proportionality, and
must not be unreasonable or excessive.
If action is taken in self-defense, no prior authorization is required
from the UN Security Council, although there is an obligation to
report to the Council any actions so taken. However, Article 51
of the UN Charter, which enshrines the customary law right to self-defense,
requires that the need for response be instant and overwhelming,
with an element of urgency leaving no time for deliberation or reflection.
The longer the U.S. waits before responding militarily to the September
11 attacks, the less it may look like pure self-defense, as the
concept is understood in international law, and the more it may
begin to appear purely retributive, and correspondingly less lawful,
in nature.
In any event it may be advisable for the sake of legality
particularly in view of the broad anti-terrorist coalition which
the U.S. is trying to create to seek a mandate from the Security
Council for an enforcement action under Chapter VII of the Charter.
Although in the past such actions have invariably been directed
against States, in view of the grave threat to international peace
and security posed by terrorism in the current crisis, there should
be no legal problem in obtaining a Security Council mandate for
an action designed to restore international peace and security by
removing the threat of terrorism. NATO actions obviously need the
mandate of the North Atlantic Council.
"Retaliation" and "revenge" are not concepts
recognised per se in the international law regulating the
resort to armed force by States; reprisals, however, are. They consist
in acts which would normally be illegal, but are in response to
prior illegal acts by another State and are undertaken with the
sole objective of securing a cessation of the prior illegal activity.
They must be preceded by an unsatisfied demand for reparation by
the injured State and must be strictly proportionate to the original
harm inflicted. Since the introduction of the UN Charter, the consensus
view of reprisals involving the use of armed force has been that
they are only lawful if they amount to actions taken in self-defense,
in which case they must comply with the legal requirements of self-defense.
Reprisals have never expressly been invoked by States in response
to international terrorism.
At present no such courts exist at the international level. The
ICTY and ICTR are limited to crimes committed in the former Yugoslavia
and Rwanda, respectively, and the ICC is not as yet operational
pending the entry into force of its Statute. In any event, none
of these institutions have or will have jurisdiction over acts of
terrorism.
1
In its decision in The Prosecutor v. Kupreskic et al. (14 January
2000), Trial Chamber II of the International Criminal Tribunal for
the Former Yugoslavia noted that, in requiring a nexus to an armed
conflict in Article 5 of the Statute, "the Security Council
may have defined the crime
more narrowly than is necessary
in customary international law"(para .545). Moreover, the definition
of crimes against humanity in Article 5 of the ICTY Statute is clearly
for the purposes of this tribunal and need not necessarily impinge
upon general customary international law. Article 7 of the 1998 Statute
of the International Criminal Court does not specify any requirement
of an armed conflict.
2 Rulke 61 Decision.
3 Paragraph 555.
4 Against a civilian population "specifically
identified as a group" (The Prosecutor v. Nikolic, para. 26).
This site © Crimes of War Project 1999-2003
|