Codifying the Unconventional
The
Swiss governments January 2003 roundtable to discuss the Geneva
Conventions and 1977 Protocols in light of the so-called war on
terrorism is now the talk among experts in international humanitarian
law. To some academics and NGOs, the discussions provide a long-overdue
opportunity to consider updating the Conventions and Protocols
to tailor them for a war they were never designed to address. In
that sense, a new round of codification would be as important a
response to terrorism as was the ICRCs diplomatic conference
of the 1970s a response to anti-colonial wars and internal conflicts.
Although
governments and other experts should ensure that the employment
of coercion against terrorists is regulated according to some normative
framework, I believe that most claims for a major reform of international
humanitarian law are premised on a variety of misconceptions of
that law. As a result, any intergovernmental process is not likely
to lead to any significant new norms nor, I believe, should it.
In this essay, I will suggest four misconceptions implicit in calls
for major reform, and their implications for efforts to augment
the Conventions and Protocols.
Misconception
1: International Humanitarian Law has a Major Gap Regarding the
War on Terror.
A common
assumption in favor of updating the law of war is that the existing
corpus of international humanitarian law is ill-equipped to address
uses of force by and against terrorist groups. While the laws of
war provide detailed rules for interstate conflicts, conflicts between
states and liberation movements, and conflicts between states and
well organized insurgencies, they do not provide any guidance to
those fighting in wars between states and terrorist movements. It
is, of course, undeniable that the Conventions and Protocols only
cover what they cover. If one side in the conflict does not meet
the definitions provided in Common Article 2 of the Geneva Conventions,
Article 1(4) of Protocol I, and Article 1 of Protocol II, the Conventions
and Protocols qua treaties simply do not govern the conflict.
But
international humanitarian law has a sizeable "place-holder"
for all other conflicts one that Protocol I explicitly recognizes:
"the principles of international law derived from established
custom, from the principles of humanity and from the dictates of
public conscience." These terms are no mere rhetoric. At a
minimum, their content includes: (a) the principle of distinction,
i.e., that combatants must distinguish between other combatants
and civilians, and that combatants must neither deliberately target
nor indiscriminately or disproportionately harm civilians; (b) the
status of hors de combat, under which combatants not taking part
in hostilities shall be treated humanely; (c) limitations on methods
of combat to those that do not cause unnecessary suffering. These
basic notions are admittedly vague around the margins. But states
have made clear that they recognize such obligations in all conflicts.
Thus, while at first denying, and later limiting, the application
of the Geneva Conventions to its operations against Afghanistan
and Al Qaeda, the United States and its allies have repeatedly stated
their acceptance of basic principles of humanitarian law.
Indeed,
the full scope of customary international humanitarian law is far
more detailed than these basic principles. If asked, most states
would point to numerous provisions of Hague and Geneva Law as still
binding on this conflict, even though it does not meet the definition
of armed conflict in those instruments. For instance, the ban on
killing someone in the course of a bona fide surrender, as well
as the possibility to shoot those engaging in perfidy by faking
surrender (with some gray areas as to how the bona fides of the
surrender is determined), would seem well accepted.
This
is not to suggest that every scenario in the "war on terrorism"
is addressed by customary international law. That, after all, is
why states draft treaties. Ambiguities over the definition of combatant,
the meaning of hostilities (and the end of them), and other problems
will remain beyond the scope of existing customary international
law simply because customary law has not had time to develop regarding
certain aspects of these new conflicts. The question, however, is
whether those ambiguities can and should be resolved through a new
round of codification, or whether other methods are open to decisionmakers.
The
burden needs to be on those calling for revision to demonstrate
exactly what needs to be improved. Are they asserting that, under
current law, combatants are underprotected, as when members of so-called
terrorist groups are taken prisoner and not granted POW status;
or that they are overprotected, as when the U.S. army targets and
kills an Al Qaeda leader in Yemen and claims this action is a legitimate
engagement in an armed conflict? Are civilians currently underprotected,
as when they are killed in collapsing buildings; or are they said
to be overprotected, because many members of terrorist cells, e.g.,
those organizing or financing activities, never wear uniforms or
ever show arms? Even now, while the United States denies the applicability
of the POW provisions of Geneva Convention III to Taliban detainees
(almost certainly unjustified under that Convention) or Al Qaeda
detainees (far more convincing under extant law), the ICRC is able
to monitor their conditions at a number of detention facilities.
More
likely, the harms arise from the prospect that states, such as the
United States, may be claiming the right to kill terrorists (as
the U.S. defines them) anywhere or detain them indefinitely. This
is a significant expansion of the notion of armed conflict, and
eats away at much of the traditional ways of addressing transnational
crime, e.g., through extradition and trial. But if that is the case,
those inside and outside of governments should focus on those narrow
issues, rather than assume that international humanitarian law has
little to say about such conflicts.
Misconception
2: Jus in Bello Can and Should be Divorced from Jus Ad
Bellum.
One
of the hallmarks of IHL since Henri Dunant has been the need to
protect victims of armed conflict regardless of its cause or the
blameworthiness of the sides under the law governing recourse to
force (jus ad bellum). Today, the Conventions and Protocols
apply equally to entities acting unlawfully in violation
of the UN Charters ban on the use of force -- and those acting
lawfully -- in self-defense, under UN authority, or in opposition
to colonial domination (or even against an unjust regime, although
international law tends to be rather agnostic on this issue). Without
such a clear distinction, combatants would argue that the justness
of their cause allows for all sorts of indignities against combatants
and civilians, clearly defeating the whole enterprise of IHL. With
regard to terrorism, the argument would be that the question of
who is right and who is wrong in the decisions by certain states
and non-state groups to use violence against each other should not
detract from the need to regulate that conflict in a humanitarian
manner.
The
jus in bello/jus ad bellum distinction is thus premised on
the idea -- based on fundamental principles of humanity -- that
all combatants and civilians deserve protections regardless of the
merits of their side. In addition, international actors may well
have other reasons for granting both sides protection. They may
understand the difficulty of knowing (or at least reaching a consensus
among states) in certain conflicts which side has violated jus
ad bellum by initiating the war; in these cases, it is better
to grant both sides protection.
But
the reality is not a clear-cut as this distinction suggests. First,
the inclusion of wars of liberation in Protocol Is coverage
stemmed from the sense among many governments that certain struggles
against colonial or alien domination were legitimate; and even Protocol
IIs protections recognize that insurgent groups might be engaging
a legitimate activity. Second, even for wars that are illegal, i.e.,
clear aggression under the UN Charter, states seem to have found
these not so obnoxious to merit denying even the offenders humanitarian
protections. States quietly accept that wars still happen; that
aggression still occurs; and that they might, after all, even be
aggressors themselves one day. They are not willing to say that
the aggressor is so evil that his goal is so beyond the pale
of civilized conduct -- that he forfeits all protections for his
troops and his civilians.
But
what happens when we have non-state actors whose goal is simply
to kill innocent people and terrorize a population? While not all
groups labeled as terrorist by states have this goal many
use attacks on civilians as a means to gain control of specific
territory (e.g., the IRA or Palestinian groups) -- there seems to
be no such goal for Al Qaeda. It has no leaders in waiting to take
over the United States or the United Kingdom. It claims to want
those states to change their foreign policies on various issues,
but there is also evidence that it is simply the way of life practiced
in these states that it finds a threat. In these situations, can
and should governments make the leap of faith that such conflict
against organized states deserves regulation by detailed protections
of international humanitarian law? When the goal of a group is so
beyond acceptable conduct that it finds no defenders among governments,
extending the protections of international humanitarian law to such
conflicts serves a legitimating function. Equally significant, key
governments likely have the same fear, and are unlikely to engage
in a process that they will regard as tarnishing IHL.
Misconception
3: The Non-Reciprocal Nature of IHL Demands Protection for Even
Those Entities That Insist on Violating it.
Another
mantra of international humanitarian law is that, unlike much international
law, the targets of its norms deserve protection even if they themselves
violate them. Thus, traditional norms of treaty interpretation that
permit a state to suspend its obligations in the event of a material
breach by the other side do not apply in many key situations. At
a minimum, reprisals i.e., otherwise unlawful acts taken
in response to prior unlawful acts -- against POWs, civilians, and
wounded, sick, and shipwrecked combatants are explicitly prohibited
by Geneva Convention III (article 13), Geneva Convention IV (article
33), and Protocol I (articles 20 and 51(6)). Some might call for
the abolition of all reprisals based on the underlying purposes
of IHL. Another form of non-reciprocity appears in Protocol Is
requirement (article 44(2)) that combatants do not lose their status
even if they violate most norms of IHL in the course of their operations.
Under this non-reciprocity model, the violations of IHL by various
terrorist groups should not be an excuse for denying them certain
protections.
But
non-reciprocity is not and should not be all-encompassing. First,
current IHL does not preclude reprisals during combat against combatants
that might violate IHL. Second, even the bans on reprisals in Protocol
I have their detractors, such as the United Kingdom, which issued
a reservation to that treaty allowing for the possibility of measured
reprisals against civilians if the opposing party itself engaged
in serious, deliberate attacks on civilians. Lastly, the granting
of protections in Protocol I was, in fact, part of a reciprocal
bargain, not simply extending protections to guerrilla groups as
a gesture of goodwill, but creating obligations for those movements
as well. Thus Protocol I denies combatant status to guerrilla groups
that do not follow certain requirements regarding open carrying
of arms.
The
nature of terrorist organizations whose modus operandi typically
includes targeting of civilians (although it is not limited to that)
pushes the need for non-reciprocity even further. One side
is determined from the outset to carry out a struggle regardless
of even the most fundamental principles of humanity. If these acts
are not simply an aberration but its principal way of operation,
why should its members be afforded anything more than treatment
consistent with those basic notions of humanity? (Some will suggest
that they do not even deserve that treatment, of course.) States
will not and should not tolerate a legal regime whereby only one
set of combatants benefits from the protections of IHL.
This
solution is not a recipe for a free-for-all in the war against terrorism.
As noted, basic principles of humanity still apply and are accepted
by governments. They would mean, for example, that terrorists cannot
be tortured upon capture and that their families cannot be targeted.
But to suggest that the IHLs non-reciprocal approach to protections
requires granting them a vast array of other protections, such as
the combatants privilege (against prosecution) or POW status,
is unwarranted.
Misconception
4: The Paradigms of Combat and Combatants are Out of Date.
One
argument made for the revision of the Conventions and Protocols
is that they reflect an outdated notion of what constitute armed
conflict and those participating in it. Thus, Al Qaedas actions
against the United States whether against civilians or military
personnel, whether within the United States or abroad are
clearly a form of armed conflict; and the U.S. actions in fighting,
capturing, and killing Al Qaeda forces whether in Afghanistan,
Pakistan, Yemen, or elsewhere are equally armed conflict.
The argument is not that customary law does not offer some protections,
but that the Conventions and Protocols, which on their face govern
only three sets of conflicts (state vs. state, state vs. national
liberation movement, and state vs. organized insurgency), need to
respond to the changing nature of armed conflict.
This
apparent need for updating seems bolstered by the very use of the
war paradigm by states engaging with Al Qaeda. Thus, the United
States and its allies have used the rhetoric of armed conflict to
respond to the attacks of September 11. U.S. officials refer to
their operations as the "war" on terrorism; and the United
States has invoked its rights under jus ad bellum
Article 51 of the United Nations Charter in attacking Afghanistan
and Al Qaeda targets and personnel around the world. The U.S. relies
on this characterization to avoid treating Al Qaeda as simply a
criminal organization that can be targeted only through traditional
law enforcement activities, e.g., police investigations, extradition
requests, and civilian trials with full due process. Advocates for
change say that the U.S. is trying to have it both ways asserting
various rights under jus ad bellum while denying the applicability
of key aspects of jus in bello.
It
seems unquestionable that the United States and others are engaged
in an armed conflict with Al Qaeda. But the subsidiary concepts
of combat operations and combatants that permeate Hague and Geneva
Law are not and should not be infinitely elastic. Part of the core
of international humanitarian law is the creation of physical and
temporal space in which it is perfectly legal for certain categories
of people to kill each other: that space is combat and those people
are combatants. The combatants privilege means that combatants
(at least in international conflicts) may not be punished for lawful
combat operations, though, of course, they can be punished for war
crimes. The notions of armed conflict, combat, and combatant have
changed since the days of the Hague Conventions, as Protocol I makes
especially clear; today, the problems of determining whether the
unconventional nature of some armed forces garb (like the
Taliban) serves to deny them combatant status are well known.
Yet,
even with the expansion of the notion of armed conflict to cover
acts by national liberation movements in Protocol I, there remain
the ideas of the military engagement and the military attack. For
instance, under Protocol I, if a fighter does not carry his arms
openly during the engagements as well as during the deployment before
an attack while visible to the adversary, he is not a lawful combatant
(entitled, for example, to POW status). This compromise (though
opposed by the United States) preserves the idea of combat operations
and the special nature of the combatant, who must distinguish himself
from the civilian population in combat and the time leading up to
it. The ban on perfidy also reinforces this idea.
To
expand the laws of wars to apply to any situation where an organization
(or conceivably an individual) initiates force is to blur the distinction
between cases where the law allows individuals to kill each other
and those where the law prohibits it. Under such a view, every attack
on a military installation, even if undertaken without any separation
from the civilian population (indeed, this is the modus operandi
of many terrorist operatives) is per se a combat operation and those
who carry it out combatants. The result is to turn every act of
violence into an act of war, and all those who commit it into lawful
combatants who enjoy the combatants privilege. It infinitely
expands the protected zone in time and space. Where does one draw
the line between Al Qaeda attacks and those of the mafia or simply
an insane person? For the combatants privilege to remain,
as it should, a hallmark of international humanitarian law, it must
be confined to a highly limited set of circumstances. States will
not and should not agree to extend it to any individual or group
that chooses to attack a military target.
Priorities
for Normative Development
Of
course, as noted, the United States government conceives of the
struggle against Al Qaeda as a war, and it wants to expand the geographical
zone of legitimate combat significantly to cover, for instance,
the killing by remotely piloted vehicle of a suspected Al Qaeda
leader in Yemen. The United States also wants to expand the notion
of combat temporally. It refuses to talk about an end to the hostilities,
partly to justify the indefinite detention without trial of Al Qaeda
and Taliban personnel.
These
two expansions of the notions of armed conflict, combat, and combatant
geographical and temporal are the most vexing questions
for IHL today. On the geographical plane, it is hard to accept the
U.S. position that treats Al Qaeda operatives around the world as
legitimate targets for wartime killing while rejecting the idea
that Al Qaeda operatives are acting as lawful combatants when they
kill U.S. soldiers anywhere in the world. The U.S. squares the circle
by relying on the notion of the "illegal combatant," something
that IHL already accepts in terms of spies, mercenaries, and guerrillas
who do not meet the special requirements of carrying arms openly.
This allows a state to kill them but afford them no protections.
But is there no limit to how and where someone becomes such an illegal
combatant?
The
simplest solution is to say that the armed conflict paradigm does
not apply at all that Al Qaedas members are criminals
and that the United States should use law enforcement techniques
to try and punish them, just like European states are rounding up
suspected members of Al Qaeda cells. Human rights law, which governs
peacetime law enforcement, still recognizes significant discretion
for police acting in genuine self-defense, while protecting criminals
from arbitrary killing by the state. The question is whether this
attitude will suffice in a world where Al Qaeda can gain access
to weapons of mass destruction. If states treat the campaign against
Al Qaeda as an armed conflict, then they need to do so in a way
that does not entail a wholesale change in the notion of combat.
The conflict with Al Qaeda needs to have boundaries beyond which
the special privileges that the law of war gives to combatants do
not apply.
As
for the temporal question, namely the U.S. willingness to tolerate
indefinite detention of Al Qaeda fighters, it is clearly unsustainable
in the long term. (As noted, their position on the Taliban seems
to be a misreading of the Conventions.) Humanitarian and human rights
law make clear that individuals whether lawful combatants,
civilians, or others -- cannot be held indefinitely without trial.
But rather than recognizing some form of combatant status for Al
Qaeda and then trying to determine at what point hostilities cease
(so that they would have to be released), another possibility is
available. They should enjoy protections consistent at a minimum
with basic principles of humanity. Beyond that, states might apply
the list of minimal protections found in Article 75 of Protocol
I to any captured terrorist. This list currently applies to anyone
in the control of a party to an interstate conflict who does not
enjoy better treatment under other parts of the Convention and Protocol.
These include the basic human right to a trial for suspected crimes.
In
summary, as a predictive matter, it seems exceedingly unlikely that
states will agree to a significant revision or augmentation of the
laws of war to address the sorts of unconventional threats posed
by transnational groups such as Al Qaeda. To date, only a very small
part of those activities that some states refer to as terrorism
guerrilla warfare as part of a legitimate war of national
liberation has come under the protection of international
humanitarian treaties. The remainder of unconventional activity
is still subject to baseline principles of humanity, and states
see little reason to grant more. Protocol I was expanded to cover
liberation movements because a group of states those in the
developing world insisted upon such protections. Al Qaeda
and other groups have no such vocal constituency, however, as much
as some states may support them sub silencio. If, for some reason,
enough states were to find the absence of treaty law in the war
on terrorism an unacceptable gap, a Protocol III is likely to be
far more limited than Protocol II turned out to be. Indeed, I suspect
it will do nothing beyond recognizing the most basic principles
of humanity.
As
a normative matter, any codification that goes beyond the obvious
principles of humanity is at best premature. The legitimization
function accomplished through codification sends a signal to these
unconventional fighters that their tactics are acceptable
that they are lawful combatants, even if they consider their great
victories to be crashing a plane into a commercial building or incapacitating
a major city via germ or chemical weapons. The immediate threat
to public order around the world from groups whose mission is to
create civilian casualties who themselves reject the most
basic principles of the law of war argues against enveloping
their activities in a set of detailed law of war norms. Any such
process will do little to protect the victims of such acts, as those
people are already illegitimate targets under international criminal
law, humanitarian law, and human rights law. So it seems to benefit
only one side in the conflict. Whatever protections those fighting
colonial domination may have deserved, Al Qaeda and its allies fall
into a completely different category.
Clearly,
states do need to figure out some limits to armed conflict as a
geographic and temporal matter, and academic and governmental discussion
of such issues can help elaborate whether the existing norms work
or need some further elaboration. But beyond that, as long as those
fighting terrorism respect the basic principles of humanity in that
struggle, international humanitarian law ought to live with something
close to the status quo.
Back
to Top
|