December
2003
Why
the United States Is So Opposed
By Paul W. Kahn
The
opposition of the United States to the International Criminal Court
appears as either a puzzle or an embarrassment to many of the nation's
traditional supporters. A puzzle, because it is not at all obvious
why the United States should feel so threatened by this new court.
Supporters of the Court point out that there are ample provisions
in the Rome Statute designed to protect a mature democracy's capacity
to engage in legal self-regulation and self-policing. To raise the
specter of an irresponsible prosecutor before the ICC, or of other
nations manipulating the Court's jurisdiction for anti-American
political purposes, is to create a straw man.
An
embarrassment, because the United States appears to be exempting
itself from rules of the game that it believes should apply to others.
This is singularly inappropriate when the game involves allegations
of crimes against humanity, genocide and war crimes. The US claim
for special status undermines the very idea of the rule of law as
a single, principled normative order to which all are bound. Even
worse, it may undermine the great international effort of the last
century to subject the use of force to the rule of law. For the
United States to take this position is particularly embarrassing,
since it, more than any other modern nation-state, has held itself
out as committed to and constituted by the rule of law.
Stuck
between the puzzle and the embarrassment, friends and allies have
few arguments with which to respond when critics offer easy political
explanations for the US position. Easiest of all is the claim that
US opposition to the Court is based upon a kind of "bad man"
view of the new regime of international criminal law. Expecting
to violate the rules, the United States wants to exempt itself from
their institutional enforcement. After all, no other nation pours
comparable resources into a defense establishment. These resources
are not being spent for no purpose. The United States pays for its
military because it intends to use it as an instrument of national
policy: witness Kosovo, Afghanistan, Iraq, and who knows where next.
With the deployment of armies come charges of aggression as well
as alleged violations of humanitarian law.
Another
easy explanation is to point to political psychology. The United
States allegedly suffers from a kind of political paranoia, a latent
tendency toward xenophobia. Sometimes this is expressed in the claim
that the opposition is "ideological," usually meaning
that it is a product of right-wing fantasies. Sometimes, an historical
element is added: US exceptionalism rests on a combination of Protestant
faith in a messianic mission and a tradition of isolationism. The
United States was founded by those fleeing the religious and political
corruption of the Old World. Solutions to old world problems are
seen as irrelevant to American life. Worse, those solutions are
tainted with the corruption of old world politics. The United States,
to its critics, has a fantasy of purity.
There
is just enough truth in each of these explanations to give them
some traction. The United States is a militarized, imperial power;
it does maintain a political culture deeply informed by Protestant
faith; it does believe that its history has been providential. But
the negative twist put on each explanation calls forth the question:
As opposed to what? Of course, American politics is self-interested.
Whose is not? Of course, American politics rests upon certain ideological
beliefs. Since when is politics not ideological? Of course, contemporary
political beliefs reflect historical experience and the larger frame
of religious beliefs held by the community. How could they not?
All
politics arises out of this mix of self-interest, ideology, history
and faith. If this produces a particularly dangerous form of politics
in the United States, then it should be opposed. But too often supporters
of the International Criminal Court seem to think that the invocation
of law is a kind of trump to politics, that it is enough to appeal
to law to win this argument. The problem with the American attitude,
they believe, is that it is a political position -- an anachronism
in the emerging global order of law. The American perception tends
to be just the opposite: invocation of international law is seen
as just another form of politics to be assessed like any other political
claim.
The
Battle Between Law and Politics
The
conflict over the Court today is so intense not because the practical
stakes are high, but because the jurisdiction of the Court has become
the site for a symbolic battle between law and politics. Supporters
of the Court tend to believe that twentieth century politics led
to the devastating violence of that century. On their view, politics
itself is dangerous; indeed, it is the source of the problem for
which the Court is to be the answer. In this new century, the politics
of vital national interests should be replaced by the managerial
and technocratic sciences of the welfare state, on the one hand,
and a regime of universal law, on the other. Both constrict the
space that remains open for the traditional politics of nation-states.
That space should extend no further than the health and well-being
of populations.
The
triumph of the West in 1989 is read not as a triumph for one political
view over another, but for managerial and administrative science.
The new western democracies are to be depoliticized spaces in which
government's role is to apply diverse forms of expertise to manage
the market and to deal with those problems resistant to market solutions.
A state that tends to the well-being of its population domestically
- increasing GDP and decreasing morbidity rates - and deals with
the rest of the world through transnational institutions and international
legal regimes has nothing to fear from this Court. The real sin
of the United States is to believe in itself as a political entity,
when the new world order is to be an order of law.
There
is nothing new in this conflict. Cosmopolitan lawyers have long
sought to impose a regime of international law on the use of force;
they have long believed that politics should be displaced by bureaucratic
management. The 20th century began in much the same way
as the 21st - with dreams of law displacing the politics
of vital, sovereign interests in a new age of reason.1 International law and
international institutions were produced in abundance, including
the Hague Conventions and the International Court of Arbitration.
After the First World War, the dream took the form of the League
of Nations, the Kellogg-Briand Pact, and the Permanent Court of
International Justice. The same dream briefly flourished between
the end of the Second World War and the start of the Cold War, producing
another set of international institutions. Of course, the end of
the Cold War reawakens the dream of the end of politics and the
age of international law.
Reasonable
men everywhere want to believe that institutions and legal rules
can control the tendency of politics to turn violent -- both internally
and externally. That dream of reason has, for 100 years, taken the
form of international law and international courts. Opposition to
this aspiration must be based on misunderstanding or self-interest,
for that is the only way in which reason can view opposition. But
there is another word for this opposition: politics. The United
States stands out in the West today because of its insistence that
politics has priority over law. It remains attached to the belief
that it is a self-determining political entity; it will not subordinate
the national will to the universal rule of reason. Politics, on
this view, is the self-expression of the sovereign nation-state.
What
is the Rule of Law?
The
character of the controversy over the Court is particularly difficult
to understand because the central term of the debate -- the rule
of law -- is itself deeply contested. American political culture
does not accept the cosmopolitan view of an opposition between law
and politics, with law cast as the expression of reason and politics
as self-interest. In the American constitutional frame, popular
sovereignty and the rule of law are a single phenomenon constitutive
of the national political identity. The rule of law, which begins
and ends in American life with the Constitution, is the self-expression
of the popular sovereign. The Constitution is the source of all
law-making power, and every assertion of a legal rule can be tested
against the Constitution. No question more quickly or easily comes
forward in our political culture than "Is it constitutional?"
Americans
believe they created themselves as a "nation under law."
That law is not a set of moral constraints imposed on the political
process from outside, whether from natural law, jus cogens,
or customary international law. Rather, the law expresses the substantive
decisions of a self-governing community. The American Constitution
expresses the will of "we the People." The rule of law
is binding on the American political community not because it is
reasonable or morally correct. It is binding because it arises out
of the constitutive act of self-creation by that community. Thus,
the rule of law is not a moral norm; rather, it is an existential
condition signifying the continuing existence of the popular sovereign.
No
one should underestimate the claim that the American Constitution
makes upon the American citizen: it defines him as a political being;
it is the object of his patriotism and the subject of a profound
reverence. Despite the charges of rampant consumerism in modern
America, the political culture maintains a cult of sacrifice - amply
demonstrated in the post 9/11 events. The Constitution is at the
very heart of this cult: in its name, Americans, for 200 years,
have willingly taken up the burden of killing and being killed.
Of
course, this does not mean that Americans are indifferent to the
moral content of their law. They want their law to be reasonable
and morally correct, but that means only that they want the community
to bind itself by laws that satisfy these standards. They want their
law to be morally satisfying in the same way that a parent wants
his or her child to be morally good: we want them to be good because
we love them; we do not love them because they are good. It is the
same with the community that is the United States: citizens have
a deep bond to the popular sovereign; because of that, they care
deeply about how it behaves. They will not easily abandon this bond,
even when they judge that behavior harshly.
The
American National Myth
The
behavior of the popular sovereign is what Americans mean by the
rule of law: the rule of law is rule by the popular sovereign. This
union of the rule of law and popular sovereignty is the great American
political achievement. Of course, all of this is true not as a matter
of fact, but as a matter of political faith. It is the American
civic religion or our national myth. Belief in the popular sovereign
as a single, transhistorical subject is at the core of the American
democratic project. That project is not about assessing the will
of a contemporary majority, but about maintaining the faith in a
single, self-governing, plural subject: the People. Not elections,
but courts claiming to speak in the voice of the People express
this core American belief. There was, in this respect, nothing puzzling
about President Bush's ascension to office through the Supreme Court's
decision. 2
We
cannot really understand the character of this sovereign subject
without appealing to the religious language that it has co-opted,
beginning with the very conception of sovereignty itself. Americans
believe that they killed the king in a revolutionary act. In place
of the mystical corpus of the King's body, they substituted the
mystical corpus of the popular sovereign. Like the God in whose
place he stands, the only access to the popular sovereign is through
the text that it produced. Our civic Bible is the Constitution --
the locus of the showing forth of the sacred people. Thus, we know
the popular sovereign by reading the product of this single, creative
act. Maintenance of the meaning of that revelatory act of the Sovereign
People is the rule of law. We are not far from the heart of Judeo-Christian
belief in this linkage of divinity to the production of law. America,
unlike Europe, remains a place of vibrant religious faith not just
in its denominational churches but in its politics as well.
American
courts may be the most powerful in the world; American citizens
may be the most litigious. Yet, American constitutional practice
is quite out of step with that of other mature democracies. Our
interpretive practice shares more with biblical hermeneutics than
with the proportionality review of other constitutional courts.
Every constitutional argument in the United States begins with the
text itself. It then advances to consider the historical intent
of the framers, and finally takes up the history of judicial interpretation
of the controverted text. These are all ways of expressing the bounded
character of our rule of law; they all point to the rule of law
as a practice of interpreting the action of the popular sovereign.
We do not think that either the text or the framers' intent is anachronistic
because we believe both are elements of a transhistorical popular
sovereign. Our rule of law gives symbolic expression to the continuous
participation of the citizen in this single, plural subject: We
the People. Like the Passover Seder that reminds the contemporary
Jew that he was with Moses in the escape from Egypt, the American
citizen is continually reminded through law that he was there at
the Founding.
The
American myth of self-creation drew simultaneously on the Enlightenment
tradition of reason and the religious tradition of the sacred quality
of the sovereign will. This combination was able to bind together
a nation of immigrants by offering all the opportunity to participate
equally in the democratic project. Again, this is not equality in
fact "the United States has been plagued by inequalities. It
is that faith in equality of all before a creator God. Americans
easily transferred this structure of faith to an ultimate concern
with a political project of popular sovereignty. This American political
faith is already clear by 1803, with Chief Justice John Marshall's
assertion of judicial supremacy" a supremacy based on the Court's
claim to speak in the name of the popular sovereign. 3 It is secured in the mass political sacrifice of the
Civil War and marked for the nation by that secular Christ figure:
Lincoln. Finally, it is wildly triumphant in the 20th
century: the American century.
The
Symbolic Threat of the ICC
This
set of beliefs fuels the dispute over the ICC. Opposition to the
Court has little to do with the substantive threat it represents
to particular American goals and little to do with a fear of political
misuse. Making reassuring arguments on these points is not going
to change the general political sentiment of opposition. After all,
the Court can never be stronger than the political commitment to
abide by the treaty. If the United States were to judge the Court
a substantial interference with vital national interests, if it
were to believe that the Court had been politically "hijacked,"
it could simply withdraw its consent. It could do this formally
under the treaty or it could simply pull out in violation of the
treaty. By agreeing to the Court, a state hardly gives up the capacity
or the need to exercise political judgment in the future. The threat
to the United States is not practical, it is symbolic. The symbolism
of the Court would displace the connection of the rule of law to
popular sovereignty. It would put in its place an idea of law founded
on the universal claims of reason. Symbolically, it would suggest
an end to the unique, American political project.
By
the end of the 20th century, much of the world saw the
modernist project of founding national identity on popular sovereignty
as quite disastrous. Everyone, from fascists, to ethnic nationalists
or authoritarian generals had claimed the right to rule in the name
of the people. The politics of popular sovereignty had led to repression
at home and violence abroad. Claims of sovereignty had been invoked
to ward off the intrusive eye of the international community; such
claims were the last refuge of abusive regimes. Arguments were now
made that the traditional concept of sovereignty was empty. In its
place, the "new sovereignty" would be located in the capacity
to engage in international institutions.
4 In the age of globalization, there was no longer
to be a distinction between the domestic and the transnational.
Thus, national politics would be replaced by transnational networks
- networks of capital, trade, information, culture, productive capacities
and even population flows.
Wherever
there is exhaustion with the politics of popular sovereignty, there
is appeal to an idea of a universal rule of law based on reason.
Is this not the lesson of the wars of Europe? The European Union
embodies this idea that the rule of law must be founded on reason
rather than on a faith in a transhistorical myth of the People.
Reason will produce a rule of law framed by an understanding of
justice, on the one hand, and administrative expertise on the other.
The International Criminal Court is just one more example of this
ideal. So is the incorporation of international human rights norms
into domestic constitutions. All of these developments express the
same rightful weariness of much of the world with the politics of
sovereignty.
Belief
in reason, however, is not an alternative to political ideology:
it is another political position. Reason's truths may be self-evident
to many in the West, but they are not universally self-evident.
For those who believe that the task of reason is the interpretation
of divine revelation - whether in the Koran or the Bible - the displacement
of politics by administration is not an appealing model at all.
Even in the West, there is not of a single view about the nature
of the political community. Claims for ethnicity compete with claims
of cosmopolitanism; claims for republican virtues compete with those
of liberalism. It is not an accident that the charge raised against
both the EU and the WTO is that of a democracy deficit. One might
vigorously disagree with the American opposition to the International
Criminal Court, but one cannot argue that this position is out of
step with American popular sentiment. There is little popular support
for the idea that American political decisions can or should be
subject to legal evaluation by non-citizens. There is no support
because the idea conflicts with the vibrant character of belief
in a rule of law that is a function of, not a measure of, popular
sovereignty.
Thus,
behind the formal dispute over the Rome Statute is a deeper dispute
over the character of law, and behind that is an even deeper dispute
over the place of sovereignty in the contemporary moment. Post 9/11,
these opposing political cultures have been forced into the open,
because, in response to a security crisis, nations fall back on
to their most ingrained patterns of belief. The United States has
responded to the attack in the pattern of the powerful, modern nation-state
that it is, while our European allies have, for the most part, responded
as post-modern transnational communities. Americans went to war,
while Europeans generally appealed to the mechanisms of international
law enforcement. The very idea of law operates quite differently
in these opposed perspectives. For Americans, the constitutional
order was to be defended by the use of force and an ethic of sacrifice;
for Europeans, law was the means of dealing with the threat.
The
United States is, in its own view, the most successful political
project in history. Apart from a cosmopolitan elite, Americans see
no reason to give up the faith that has fueled this triumph. There
is, however, no reason whatsoever to believe that others will share
this faith. There is every reason to doubt that this faith offers
a ground for the contemporary exercise of American power abroad
with which others will agree. But before anyone can hope to shift
American policy, they need to understand the political faith upon
which it rests. At the center of that faith is belief in the rule
of law as rule by the popular sovereign.
1 See M. Koskenniemi,
Gentle Civilizer of Nations: The Rise and Fall of International
Law 1870-1960 (2002).
2 Doctrinally, there was
much that was puzzling about the decision, but as an assertion of
power, it was not controversial. Even Al Gore acknowledged the legitimacy
of this power.
3 Marbury v. Madison,
5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137 (1803).
4 See, e.g., A. Chayes
and A. Chayes, The New Sovereignty: Compliance with International
Regulatory Agreements (1995).
Paul
W. Kahn is Robert W. Winner Professor of Law and the Humanities
at Yale Law School and Director of the Orville H. Schell, Jr. Center
for International Human Rights.
This site © Crimes of War Project 1999-2003
|